Written by: Ho Shao Rui, Edited by: Andre Koh

Wisdom/Love

Philosophia. The Greeks were friends and lovers (“philein”) of Wisdom (“sophia”). Passion was on the side of the claimant, and Wisdom the Platonic ideal itself: one has to climb the mountain of erudition to see clearly. A reversal of the terms, then, seems to be a reversal of altitude as well. Rather than striving towards the height of Reason, one descends into the pit of Unreason. Indeed, how could there be a wisdom of Love? Is this farce not a laughable attempt at wordplay? “Do not all charms fly/ At the mere touch of cold philosophy?”[1] However, let us not be so hasty. There may yet be insights into Wisdom the Lover can offer to the Philosopher. Thus, in this essay, let us stay with this oxymoron a little longer.

The realm of Eros is a strange land with strange characteristics. Time is convoluted here. Opposed to logicians who follow axioms and rules of inference, the Lover finds the reasons for love always after being in love. One can immediately see this is true. “I love him because he is funny, kind, and understanding…” No doubt these are reasons. However, one does not conduct a cost-benefit analysis or research meticulously about the positive qualities of a partner before deciding to love someone. Love sows the reasons for love retroactively. We see that the system of arithmetic is different here as well. The whole is always greater than the sum of its parts. Let us repeat the example, “I love her because she is funny, kind, and understanding…” Despite these enumerable qualities, one cannot dissect their love and say, “Out of the 100 units of love I have for my Beloved, I can divide it into 33.33 units for the comedian, the nun and my therapist!” Nor does it seem that 1=1. The Lover does not love everyone who is funny, kind and understanding, they love only their Beloved.[2] There is much more to discuss about these peculiar aspects, but that remains for another day. The brief observations here are to inform us that conventional methods of analysis do not apply in this realm. To determine whether there is any wisdom to Love, we must go further. At the heart of Love lies two epistemological questions: 1) “Do I really know my Beloved?”, 2) “Does my Beloved really know me?” These two questions shall occupy us for the remainder of this essay.


[1] John Keats, Lamia

[2] In the concrete definition of the subject, we may say that the subject falls into the predicate, or, that the subject is subsumed by the predicate. Take the statement, “God is the absolute being.”. In this statement, God is no longer self-determining, but rather defined by the predicate “absolute being”. Love here reverses this relationship. The mundane is raised to the level of a privileged object, i.e. it is predicated of itself. The Lover says, “I love her for her.”, regardless of the Beloved’s concrete attributes. In fact, we need no winding exposition to understand this. Was it not most clearly displayed by The Rose in Antoine de Saint-Exupéry’s The Little Prince?

There is an impassible ravine between theories and empirical evidence. In essence, empirical evidence is fallible, and thus, theories are neither provable nor disprovable.[1] The great twentieth-century philosophers of science have all negotiated with this disjunction in their own ways. However, we cannot take from them anything except this painful realization. Their approaches do not suffice in our investigation here. The Lover in their pursuit is exceedingly demanding: they accept only the absolute. They will not make do with probable theories, nor are they content with conventions. They demand to know that their love is true and that their image of their Beloved is true. So how should the Lover proceed? Suppose they have been with their Beloved for ages. Every day, they go through the routines they have been through countless of times: meals at home together, grocery shopping after work, evening walks in the park, weekend outings to the movies… They might even be able to finish each other’s sentences, have little in-jokes with one another: a whole secret language that only the two of them know. All this, however, does not suffice as proof. What we took from the philosophy of science is that the image of their Beloved and these concrete instances run in two parallel series. The Lover cannot simply take these instances as evidence that they know their Beloved. Underneath the pristine surface that is their image of their Beloved, there are rapid undercurrents, wholly unseen and unseeable movements of an inner subjectivity. The Lover cannot positively know their Beloved. They cannot take the surface for the depths. Thus, let us turn to the negative.

Suppose at the end of a film, the Lover caught, in the corner of their eyes, a tear flowing down from the cheek of their restrained, stoic Beloved. Imagine their disbelief! “My love? Someone whom I’ve never seen cry in our 15 years together, shed a tear watching a children’s animated film?” Setting aside their shock (and perhaps, their subsequent teasing), is it not precisely such moments which reveal the unknowability of their Beloved? Sure, theories are never unequivocally disproved by such instances. The Lover can always come up with ad hoc rescues to save themselves. “Perhaps, something happened at work today... Oh, she must have just been tired.” However, it is clear that these, too, will not suffice. In such moments, the Beloved is no longer a mere cliché; they become alive. The moments point towards a being beneath and beyond the surface of my knowing, to something that I shall never touch. Furthermore, it is at this point where the ruptured image points beyond itself, that the Lover is also reflected out of the image and back into themselves. The rupture reveals to me that it is my image, my Beloved. In our example, the contradicted predicates “restrained” and “stoic” at first appeared in the Lover’s eyes as distortions on an otherwise perfect, long-held image of their Beloved. The reflection back into themselves is the moment of realization that these predicates appear as such only from their subjective point of view: these are attributes which they have unilaterally imposed, on an image which they have singlehandedly painted. Etched on the surface are not signifiers of their Beloved, but their own ideals, comprehensions, and desires. Much like with Holbein’s The Ambassadors or Velázquez’s Las Meninas[2], the Lover is as much in the image of their Beloved as the image is beheld by them. That is to say, “The picture is in my eye, but me, I am in the picture.”[3]


[1] Imre Lakatos, Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.

[2] Of course, the compositions of the two paintings are different: the skull in The Ambassadors and the mirror, or canvas, in Las Meninas have different functions. However, the crucial factor we are considering here is that, while unbeknownst to them, the subject’s perspective is included and reflected in the image or perception itself.

[3] Slavoj Žižek, Less than Nothing. See chapter 10 on his discussion of the gaze, or p. 702-708 on the above quote. See also, Jacque Lacan, The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis, for Lacan’s original conception.

With that, we find ourselves on the other side of our problem. Perhaps one may think, with what we have discussed in the previous paragraph, that nothing more needs to be said here. Indeed, following the above, we must conclude that the Lover cannot know whether their Beloved knows them. However, so far we have viewed the situation from the perspective of the individual. Let us take the place of a phenomenological observer and see what this asymmetry entails. The individual is simultaneously both finite and infinite. They are infinite because they can set before their mind infinite objects. Yet, they are finite because they cannot fully set themselves before their minds. Unphilosophically, we might say that a “little bit” of them remains from which they do the thinking. That is to say, the individual is necessarily blind to a part of themselves. We shall refer to an example again. Imagine the Lover in their most joyous, or most wrathful moments. In such moments a million and one thoughts may rush through their heads. Still, their emotions might grant them a moment of lucidity. Nevertheless, regardless of how well they know the contents of their thoughts, they are not conscious of the thinking or acting out of such thoughts. One’s Beloved, however, bears witness to these moments. They see the idiosyncratic celebrations in joy and the venomous spite in resentment; they see the nape of one’s soul. Thus, taking this in conjunction with what we have said earlier, we ought to make a correction. The Lover’s image of their Beloved may indeed be correct, or at least, aspects of it, as in such moments. However, as mentioned above, they can never know whether this is the case. The analogous scenario in scientific inquiry is the possibility that a theory stumbles upon a necessity or natural law: the theory will never know whether it ever did so.[1]      

So, what then? Having only spoken of the negative, limitations and failures, were we not excessively harsh with Love? Additionally, it seems that there is nothing that Love could offer us. All this will be true if we simply stopped here — we will not. Nor shall we desert our established positions: the Beloved will forever be an Other to the Lover. Yet, one should not despair over this. For a love between two individuals, how could it ever be otherwise?[2] Furthermore, we ought to remind ourselves that we are, after all, in foreign land. Impossibilities may weigh one down on their ascent towards Reason. Here, however, such things have no force. The unknowability of the Beloved simply doesn’t matter. One might even say, in a Kierkegaardian manner, that Love is this paradox — or else love has never existed just because it has always existed.[3] Thus, let us see this movement play itself out to its conclusion. The Lovers finds the image of their Beloved falsified. They recognize it as their own image, one writ in water. In this is also an intimation of the inner subjectivity of their Beloved and of the infinite distance between them. The action proper to the realm of Eros, is that the Lovers love in spite of this. It is in this commitment to Love, recognizing this uncrossable distance, that the Lovers at once traverse it. They supersede it simply by their mutual recognition. That is, despite the ineptitude of any predicate expressing their Beloved, they do come to know each other: they know each other by the nothingness of these predicates.[4]


[1] See Lakatos’ Necessity, Kneale and Popper, for his discussion of Popper’s and Kneale’s perspectives on natural and physical necessity. 

[2] I am not speaking of a love between parent and child, or an individual’s love for their pet. Additionally, some popular science fiction ideas allow for individuals to link their consciousnesses and fully immerse oneself in the inner world of the other. The Beloved in such instances becomes an object of adoration for the Lover who has full comprehension of them. This, to me, is not love.

[3] Søren Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling. See Problema I and II for his discussion of the absolute in contrast to the ethical and the universal. Kierkegaard repeatedly emphasises the paradoxical nature of faith throughout the text. The movement of Love that we discuss here is similar in its sublation of its moments. In Love and Faith, the individual is higher than the universal. However, the crucial difference (in my view) lies in how the universal is sublated. Love is wholly immanent, it supersedes the universal, i.e. the concrete predicates, in the recognition that it can never go beyond them. The immanent needs no external ground nor guarantee. Whereas for the Kierkegaardian knight of faith, the subject’s relationship with the absolute is precisely that which goes beyond the realm of the ethical or the universal. (However, I must admit I haven’t quite flesh out the difference for myself.)

[4] We may even say that to recognize the Lover is to see the “the Night of the World” in them. To quote his famous passage, “The human being is this Night, this empty nothing which contains everything in its simplicity – a wealth of infinitely many representations, images, none of which occur to it directly, and none of which are not present. This [is] the Night, the interior of [human] nature, existing here – pure Self – [and] in phantasmagoric representations it is night everywhere: here a bloody head suddenly shoots up and there another white shape, only to disappear as suddenly. We see this Night when we look a human being in the eye, looking into a Night which turns terrifying. [For from his eyes] the night of the world hangs out toward us.”, G. W. F. Hegel’s The Philosophy of Spirit (Jena Lectures 1805-6).

The wisdom of Love, then, is that the recognition of impossibility is the very transcendence of it.[1]


[1] Granted, this is no news for dialectical philosophies. However, Love is the demonstration of it. In fact, doesn’t it occupy the position of Absolute Knowledge? Where, rather than being the knowledge of absolutely everything, it is the recognition that the subject is itself the absolute, transcendental horizon of knowledge. This negative, is then grasped in its concreteness as a determinate moment, i.e. in its positivity. See G. W. F. Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit.

References

Imre Lakatos, John Worrall, and Gregory Currie. 1992. Philosophical Papers. Volume 1, the Methodology of Scientific Research Programme. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Slavoj Žižek. 2012. Less than Nothing: Hegel and the Shadow of Dialectical Materialism. London: Verso; New York.

Søren Kierkegaard. 1985. Fear and Trembling. Harmondsworth: Penguin.